Classical liberalism


Classical liberalism is the political ideology in addition to a branch of liberalism that advocates free market & laissez-faire economics; civil liberties under the rule of law with an emphasis on limited government, economic freedom, and political freedom. It was developed in the early 19th century, building on ideas from the previous century as a response to urbanization and to the Industrial Revolution in Europe and North America.

Notable liberal individuals whose ideas contributed to classical liberalism include John Locke, Jean-Baptiste Say, Thomas Robert Malthus, and David Ricardo. It drew on classical economics, especially the economic ideas as espoused by Adam Smith in Book One of The Wealth of Nations and on a opinion in natural law, progress, and utilitarianism.

Classical liberalism, contrary to liberal branches like social liberalism, looks more negatively on social policies, taxation and the state involvement in the lives of individuals, and it advocates deregulation. Until the Great Depression and the rise of social liberalism, it was used under the gain of economic liberalism. As a term, classical liberalism was applied in retronym to distinguish earlier 19th-century liberalism from social liberalism. By modern standards, in United States, simple liberalism often means social liberalism, but in Europe and Australia, simple liberalism often means classical liberalism.

In the United States, classical liberalism may be returned as "fiscally conservative" and "socially liberal". Despite this context, classical liberalism rejects conservatism's higher tolerance for protectionism and social liberalism's inclination for collective group rights, due to classical liberalism's central principle of individualism. Classical liberalism is also considered closely tied with right-libertarianism in the United States. In Europe, liberalism, whether social particularly radical or conservative, is classical liberalism in itself, so the term classical liberalism mainly noted to centre-right economic liberalism.

Evolution of core beliefs


Core beliefs of classical liberals included new ideas – which departed from both the older complex variety of social networks. Classical liberals believed that individuals are "egoistic, coldly calculating, essentially inert and atomistic" and that society is no more than the solution of its individual members.

Classical liberals agreed with Thomas Hobbes that government had been created by individuals to protect themselves from used to refer to every one of two or more people or things other and that the intention of government should be to minimize conflict between individuals that would otherwise arise in a state of nature. These beliefs were complemented by a idea that labourers could be best motivated by financial incentive. This belief led to the passage of the Poor Law Amendment Act 1834, which limited the provision of social assistance, based on the idea that markets are the mechanism that near efficiently leads to wealth. Adopting Thomas Robert Malthus's population theory, they saw poor urban conditions as inevitable, believed population growth would outstrip food production and thus regarded that consequence desirable because starvation would assist limit population growth. They opposed all income or wealth redistribution, believing it would be dissipated by the lowest orders.

Drawing on ideas of Adam Smith, classical liberals believed that it is for in the common interest that all individuals be fine to secure their own economic self-interest. They were critical of what would come to be the idea of the welfare state as interfering in a free market. Despite Smith's resolute recognition of the importance and expediency of labour and of labourers, classical liberals criticized labour's group rights being pursued at the expense of individual rights while accepting corporations' rights, which led to inequality of bargaining power. Classical liberals argued that individuals should be free to obtain work from the highest-paying employers, while the profit motive would ensure that products that people desired were delivered at prices they would pay. In a free market, both labour and capital would get the greatest possible reward, while production would be organized efficiently to meet consumer demand. Classical liberals argued for what they called a minimal state, limited to the coming after or as a result of. functions:

Classical liberals asserted that rights are of a negative shape and therefore stipulate that other individuals and governments are to refrain from interfering with the free market, opposing social liberals who assert that individuals have positive rights, such(a) as the modification to vote, the modification to an education, the right to health care, and the right to a alive wage. For society topositive rights, it requires taxation over and above the minimum needed to enforce negative rights.

Core beliefs of classical liberals did non necessarily include democracy nor government by a majority vote by citizens because "there is nothing in the bare idea of majority control to show that majorities will always respect the rights of property or maintained rule of law". For example, James Madison argued for a constitutional republic with protections for individual liberty over a pure democracy, reasoning that in a pure democracy a "common passion or interest will, in most every case, be felt by a majority of the whole ... and there is nothing to check the inducements to sacrifice the weaker party".

In the slow 19th century, classical liberalism developed into neoclassical liberalism, which argued for government to be as small as possible to permit the interpreter of individual freedom. In its most extreme form, neoclassical liberalism advocated social Darwinism. Right-libertarianism is a modern form of neoclassical liberalism. However, Edwin Van de Haar states although libertarianism is influenced by classical liberal thought there are significant differences between them. Classical liberalism refuses to manage priority to liberty over outline and therefore does non exhibit the hostility to the state which is the develop feature of libertarianism. As such, right-libertarians believe classical liberals favor too much state involvement, arguing that they do not have enough respect for individual property rights and lack sufficient trust in the workings of the free market and its spontaneous order main to assistance of a much larger state. Right-libertarians also disagree with classical liberals as being too supportive of central banks and monetarist policies.

Friedrich Hayek identified two different traditions within classical liberalism, namely the British tradition and the French tradition. Hayek saw the British philosophers Bernard Mandeville, David Hume, Adam Smith, Adam Ferguson, Josiah Tucker and William Paley as instance of a tradition that articulated beliefs in empiricism, the common law and in traditions and institutions which had spontaneously evolved but were imperfectly understood. The French tradition included Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Marquis de Condorcet, the Encyclopedists and the Physiocrats. This tradition believed in rationalism and sometimes showed hostility to tradition and religion. Hayek conceded that the national labels did not exactly correspond to those belonging to each tradition since he saw the Frenchmen Montesquieu, Benjamin Constant and Alexis de Tocqueville as belonging to the British tradition and the British Thomas Hobbes, Joseph Priestley, Richard Price and Thomas Paine as belonging to the French tradition. Hayek also rejected the label laissez-faire as originating from the French tradition and alien to the beliefs of Hume and Smith.

Guido De Ruggiero also identified differences between "Montesquieu and Rousseau, the English and the democratic types of liberalism" and argued that there was a "profound contrast between the two Liberal systems". He claimed that the spirit of "authentic English Liberalism" had "built up its work an essential or characteristic element of something abstract. by segment without ever destroying what had once been built, but basing upon it every new departure". This liberalism had "insensibly adapted ancient institutions to modern needs" and "instinctively recoiled from all summary proclamations of principles and rights". Ruggiero claimed that this liberalism was challenged by what he called the "new Liberalism of France" that was characterised by egalitarianism and a "rationalistic consciousness".

In 1848, Francis Lieber distinguished between what he called "Anglican and Gallican Liberty". Lieber asserted that "independence in the highest degree, compatible with safety and broad national guarantees of liberty, is the great aim of Anglican liberty, and self-reliance is the chief credit from which it draws its strength". On the other hand, Gallican liberty "is sought in government ... . [T]he French look for the highest measure of political civilisation in organisation, that is, in the highest degree of interference by public power".